Stanley Cavell on What We Say

In his early essay, “Must We Mean What We Say”, Cavell argues that the claims of ordinary language philosophers regarding “what we say when” are not empirical generalizations about a given group of speakers but are rather to be understood as measuring the limits of what counts as a coherent act of...

Descripción completa

Guardado en:
Detalles Bibliográficos
Autor principal: Arata Hamawaki
Formato: article
Lenguaje:EN
Publicado: MULPress 2021
Materias:
Acceso en línea:https://doaj.org/article/68ad7b6009e645219a6e2df9804238d9
Etiquetas: Agregar Etiqueta
Sin Etiquetas, Sea el primero en etiquetar este registro!
id oai:doaj.org-article:68ad7b6009e645219a6e2df9804238d9
record_format dspace
spelling oai:doaj.org-article:68ad7b6009e645219a6e2df9804238d92021-11-07T13:00:28ZStanley Cavell on What We Say10.15173/jhap.v9i9.49152159-0303https://doaj.org/article/68ad7b6009e645219a6e2df9804238d92021-11-01T00:00:00Zhttps://jhaponline.org/jhap/article/view/4915https://doaj.org/toc/2159-0303 In his early essay, “Must We Mean What We Say”, Cavell argues that the claims of ordinary language philosophers regarding “what we say when” are not empirical generalizations about a given group of speakers but are rather to be understood as measuring the limits of what counts as a coherent act of thinking and speaking. Cavell’s charge against the skeptic about the external world is that he seeks to think and speak beyond these limits. In this paper I compare Cavell’s response to the skeptic to Davidson’s. Both base their responses on a broadly Kantian approach that appeals to the conditions under which thinking or speaking about objects is possible. On this approach the skeptic isn’t giving a false answer to an intelligible question, but rather, the question to which the skeptic is giving an answer is shown to be in some way unintelligible. But while Davidson’s critique of the skeptic is based on the conditions of ascribing meaning to one’s words, and contents to one’s beliefs, Cavell’s critique is based on the failure of the skeptic to mean the words he uses in the way that he needs. This difference expresses an underlying disagreement about the meaning of “meaning”: for Davidson the world comes into view through the meaning of our words and concepts, through the contents of our beliefs; for Cavell, the world comes into view through the agreement in “criteria” that are a condition of applying words and concepts to the world. This difference illuminates what Cavell calls “the truth of skepticism”: the idea that “my relation to the world and to others in general is not one of knowing”. Arata HamawakiMULPressarticlePhilosophy (General)B1-5802ENJournal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, Vol 9, Iss 9 (2021)
institution DOAJ
collection DOAJ
language EN
topic Philosophy (General)
B1-5802
spellingShingle Philosophy (General)
B1-5802
Arata Hamawaki
Stanley Cavell on What We Say
description In his early essay, “Must We Mean What We Say”, Cavell argues that the claims of ordinary language philosophers regarding “what we say when” are not empirical generalizations about a given group of speakers but are rather to be understood as measuring the limits of what counts as a coherent act of thinking and speaking. Cavell’s charge against the skeptic about the external world is that he seeks to think and speak beyond these limits. In this paper I compare Cavell’s response to the skeptic to Davidson’s. Both base their responses on a broadly Kantian approach that appeals to the conditions under which thinking or speaking about objects is possible. On this approach the skeptic isn’t giving a false answer to an intelligible question, but rather, the question to which the skeptic is giving an answer is shown to be in some way unintelligible. But while Davidson’s critique of the skeptic is based on the conditions of ascribing meaning to one’s words, and contents to one’s beliefs, Cavell’s critique is based on the failure of the skeptic to mean the words he uses in the way that he needs. This difference expresses an underlying disagreement about the meaning of “meaning”: for Davidson the world comes into view through the meaning of our words and concepts, through the contents of our beliefs; for Cavell, the world comes into view through the agreement in “criteria” that are a condition of applying words and concepts to the world. This difference illuminates what Cavell calls “the truth of skepticism”: the idea that “my relation to the world and to others in general is not one of knowing”.
format article
author Arata Hamawaki
author_facet Arata Hamawaki
author_sort Arata Hamawaki
title Stanley Cavell on What We Say
title_short Stanley Cavell on What We Say
title_full Stanley Cavell on What We Say
title_fullStr Stanley Cavell on What We Say
title_full_unstemmed Stanley Cavell on What We Say
title_sort stanley cavell on what we say
publisher MULPress
publishDate 2021
url https://doaj.org/article/68ad7b6009e645219a6e2df9804238d9
work_keys_str_mv AT aratahamawaki stanleycavellonwhatwesay
_version_ 1718443491620552704