Galileo’s paradox and numerosities

Galileo's paradox of infinity involves comparing the set of natural numbers, N, and the set of squares, {n2 : n ∈ N}. Galileo (1638) sets up a one-to-one correspondence between these sets; on this basis, the number of the elements of N is considered to be equal to the number of the elements of...

Descripción completa

Guardado en:
Detalles Bibliográficos
Autor principal: Piotr Błaszczyk
Formato: article
Lenguaje:DE
EN
FR
PL
Publicado: Copernicus Center Press 2021
Materias:
Acceso en línea:https://doaj.org/article/803947dad5b04394bd1d76acb1d98b7e
Etiquetas: Agregar Etiqueta
Sin Etiquetas, Sea el primero en etiquetar este registro!
id oai:doaj.org-article:803947dad5b04394bd1d76acb1d98b7e
record_format dspace
spelling oai:doaj.org-article:803947dad5b04394bd1d76acb1d98b7e2021-11-07T14:01:44ZGalileo’s paradox and numerosities0867-82862451-0602https://doaj.org/article/803947dad5b04394bd1d76acb1d98b7e2021-11-01T00:00:00Zhttps://zfn.edu.pl/index.php/zfn/article/view/527https://doaj.org/toc/0867-8286https://doaj.org/toc/2451-0602Galileo's paradox of infinity involves comparing the set of natural numbers, N, and the set of squares, {n2 : n ∈ N}. Galileo (1638) sets up a one-to-one correspondence between these sets; on this basis, the number of the elements of N is considered to be equal to the number of the elements of {n2 : n ∈ N}. It also characterizes the set of squares as smaller than the set of natural numbers, since ``there are many more numbers than squares". As a result, it concludes that infinities cannot be compared in terms of greater--lesser and the law of trichotomy does not apply to them. Cantor's cardinal numbers provide a measure for sets. Cantor (1897) gives a definition of the relation greater–lesser between cardinal numbers and establishes the law of trichotomy for these numbers. Yet, when Cantor's theory is applied to subsets of N, it gives that any set can be either finite or of the power ℵ0. Thus, although the set of squares is the subset of N, they are of the same cardinality. Benci, Di Nasso (2019) introduces specific numbers to measure sets called numerosities. With numerosities, the following claim is true: numerosity of A < numerosity of B, whenever A ⊈ B. In this paper, we present a simplified version of the theory of numerosities that applies to subsets of N. This theory complies with Galileo's presupposition that when A ⊈ B, then the number of elements in A is smaller than the number of elements in B. Specifically, we show that as the numerosity of N is the number α, the numerosity of the set of squares is the integer part of the number √α, that is ⌊√α⌋, and the inequality ⌊√α⌋ < α holds.Piotr BłaszczykCopernicus Center Pressarticlenon-standard real numbersnumerositiescardinal numbersgalileo's paradoxPhilosophy (General)B1-5802DEENFRPLZagadnienia Filozoficzne w Nauce, Vol 70, Pp 73-107 (2021)
institution DOAJ
collection DOAJ
language DE
EN
FR
PL
topic non-standard real numbers
numerosities
cardinal numbers
galileo's paradox
Philosophy (General)
B1-5802
spellingShingle non-standard real numbers
numerosities
cardinal numbers
galileo's paradox
Philosophy (General)
B1-5802
Piotr Błaszczyk
Galileo’s paradox and numerosities
description Galileo's paradox of infinity involves comparing the set of natural numbers, N, and the set of squares, {n2 : n ∈ N}. Galileo (1638) sets up a one-to-one correspondence between these sets; on this basis, the number of the elements of N is considered to be equal to the number of the elements of {n2 : n ∈ N}. It also characterizes the set of squares as smaller than the set of natural numbers, since ``there are many more numbers than squares". As a result, it concludes that infinities cannot be compared in terms of greater--lesser and the law of trichotomy does not apply to them. Cantor's cardinal numbers provide a measure for sets. Cantor (1897) gives a definition of the relation greater–lesser between cardinal numbers and establishes the law of trichotomy for these numbers. Yet, when Cantor's theory is applied to subsets of N, it gives that any set can be either finite or of the power ℵ0. Thus, although the set of squares is the subset of N, they are of the same cardinality. Benci, Di Nasso (2019) introduces specific numbers to measure sets called numerosities. With numerosities, the following claim is true: numerosity of A < numerosity of B, whenever A ⊈ B. In this paper, we present a simplified version of the theory of numerosities that applies to subsets of N. This theory complies with Galileo's presupposition that when A ⊈ B, then the number of elements in A is smaller than the number of elements in B. Specifically, we show that as the numerosity of N is the number α, the numerosity of the set of squares is the integer part of the number √α, that is ⌊√α⌋, and the inequality ⌊√α⌋ < α holds.
format article
author Piotr Błaszczyk
author_facet Piotr Błaszczyk
author_sort Piotr Błaszczyk
title Galileo’s paradox and numerosities
title_short Galileo’s paradox and numerosities
title_full Galileo’s paradox and numerosities
title_fullStr Galileo’s paradox and numerosities
title_full_unstemmed Galileo’s paradox and numerosities
title_sort galileo’s paradox and numerosities
publisher Copernicus Center Press
publishDate 2021
url https://doaj.org/article/803947dad5b04394bd1d76acb1d98b7e
work_keys_str_mv AT piotrbłaszczyk galileosparadoxandnumerosities
_version_ 1718443432217673728