From Galileo to Navier and Clapeyron

Galileo (1564-1642), in his well-known Discorsi (Galileo, 1638), briefly turning his attention to the fracture of a beam, starts an interesting discussion on the beam’s breakage as well as its location. Could the section and breaking point of a beam have been determined beforehand? Furthermore, is i...

Descripción completa

Guardado en:
Detalles Bibliográficos
Autor principal: Josep Maria Pons
Formato: article
Lenguaje:EN
ES
FR
Publicado: Universidad de Salamanca 2021
Materias:
Acceso en línea:https://doaj.org/article/b91d0b113b974081bc4e85e3edd61cc1
Etiquetas: Agregar Etiqueta
Sin Etiquetas, Sea el primero en etiquetar este registro!
id oai:doaj.org-article:b91d0b113b974081bc4e85e3edd61cc1
record_format dspace
spelling oai:doaj.org-article:b91d0b113b974081bc4e85e3edd61cc12021-11-30T09:53:29ZFrom Galileo to Navier and Clapeyron1989-361210.14201/art2021102520https://doaj.org/article/b91d0b113b974081bc4e85e3edd61cc12021-11-01T00:00:00Zhttps://revistas.usal.es/index.php/artefactos/article/view/25221https://doaj.org/toc/1989-3612Galileo (1564-1642), in his well-known Discorsi (Galileo, 1638), briefly turning his attention to the fracture of a beam, starts an interesting discussion on the beam’s breakage as well as its location. Could the section and breaking point of a beam have been determined beforehand? Furthermore, is it specific to the material? What Galileo did was not merely challenge a physics problem, but the prevailing knowledge of his time: namely, Aristotelianism on one hand, and Nominalism on the other. As a matter of fact, must the breakage of an element be treated as a universal or is it particular to a given material? The present essay aims to prove how Galileo, confronting the structural problem and bringing it into the realm of science, was not just raising a problem but, using Salviati’s words, he also established what actually takes place. Many years later, with the progress of physics, strength of materials and theory of structures, figures such as Claude Navier (1785-1836) and Benoît Clapeyron (1799-1864) confirmed once again that the Pisan turned out to be right. This article intends to combine technical fields such as strength of materials and theory of structures with others like the history of science and philosophy proper. A cooperative approach to these disciplines can be doubtlessly helpful to improve the knowledge, learning and teaching of their different curricula, giving the reader a global, holistic perspective.Josep Maria PonsUniversidad de Salamancaarticlearistotelian legacyscientific revolutionpisandiscorsibeamTechnology (General)T1-995Social sciences (General)H1-99ENESFRArtefactos, Vol 10, Iss 2, Pp 5-20 (2021)
institution DOAJ
collection DOAJ
language EN
ES
FR
topic aristotelian legacy
scientific revolution
pisan
discorsi
beam
Technology (General)
T1-995
Social sciences (General)
H1-99
spellingShingle aristotelian legacy
scientific revolution
pisan
discorsi
beam
Technology (General)
T1-995
Social sciences (General)
H1-99
Josep Maria Pons
From Galileo to Navier and Clapeyron
description Galileo (1564-1642), in his well-known Discorsi (Galileo, 1638), briefly turning his attention to the fracture of a beam, starts an interesting discussion on the beam’s breakage as well as its location. Could the section and breaking point of a beam have been determined beforehand? Furthermore, is it specific to the material? What Galileo did was not merely challenge a physics problem, but the prevailing knowledge of his time: namely, Aristotelianism on one hand, and Nominalism on the other. As a matter of fact, must the breakage of an element be treated as a universal or is it particular to a given material? The present essay aims to prove how Galileo, confronting the structural problem and bringing it into the realm of science, was not just raising a problem but, using Salviati’s words, he also established what actually takes place. Many years later, with the progress of physics, strength of materials and theory of structures, figures such as Claude Navier (1785-1836) and Benoît Clapeyron (1799-1864) confirmed once again that the Pisan turned out to be right. This article intends to combine technical fields such as strength of materials and theory of structures with others like the history of science and philosophy proper. A cooperative approach to these disciplines can be doubtlessly helpful to improve the knowledge, learning and teaching of their different curricula, giving the reader a global, holistic perspective.
format article
author Josep Maria Pons
author_facet Josep Maria Pons
author_sort Josep Maria Pons
title From Galileo to Navier and Clapeyron
title_short From Galileo to Navier and Clapeyron
title_full From Galileo to Navier and Clapeyron
title_fullStr From Galileo to Navier and Clapeyron
title_full_unstemmed From Galileo to Navier and Clapeyron
title_sort from galileo to navier and clapeyron
publisher Universidad de Salamanca
publishDate 2021
url https://doaj.org/article/b91d0b113b974081bc4e85e3edd61cc1
work_keys_str_mv AT josepmariapons fromgalileotonavierandclapeyron
_version_ 1718406705651384320