On the Origin, Nature, and Genesis of Habit
This article details fundamental aspects of habits, beginning with the fact that habits are dynamic patterns that are learned, and that in coincidence with this learning, habits of mind are formed, as in the formation of expectations, thus of certain if/then relationships. It points out that, in qu...
Guardado en:
Autor principal: | |
---|---|
Formato: | article |
Lenguaje: | EN FR IT |
Publicado: |
Rosenberg & Sellier
2016
|
Materias: | |
Acceso en línea: | https://doaj.org/article/c44f8a55c2534c70a8a488e0f4fa208c |
Etiquetas: |
Agregar Etiqueta
Sin Etiquetas, Sea el primero en etiquetar este registro!
|
id |
oai:doaj.org-article:c44f8a55c2534c70a8a488e0f4fa208c |
---|---|
record_format |
dspace |
spelling |
oai:doaj.org-article:c44f8a55c2534c70a8a488e0f4fa208c2021-12-02T09:29:57ZOn the Origin, Nature, and Genesis of Habit10.13128/Phe_Mi-195532280-78532239-4028https://doaj.org/article/c44f8a55c2534c70a8a488e0f4fa208c2016-11-01T00:00:00Zhttps://oaj.fupress.net/index.php/pam/article/view/7147https://doaj.org/toc/2280-7853https://doaj.org/toc/2239-4028 This article details fundamental aspects of habits, beginning with the fact that habits are dynamic patterns that are learned, and that in coincidence with this learning, habits of mind are formed, as in the formation of expectations, thus of certain if/then relationships. It points out that, in quite the opposite manner of the practice of phenomenology, the strange is made familiar in the formation of habits. It shows how clear-sighted recognition of the seminal significance of movement and phenomenologically-grounded understandings of movement are essential to understandings of habits and the habits of mind that go with them. The article differentiates non-developmentally achieved habits from developmentally achieved habits, but elucidates too the relationship between instincts and habits. It elucidates the relationship in part by showing how, contra Merleau-Ponty, “in man” there is a “natural sign”—or rather, natural signs. By relinquishing an adultist stance and delving into our common infancy and early childhood, we recognize the need for what Husserl terms a “regressive inquiry” and thereby recover ‘natural signs’ such as smiling, laughing, and crying. At the same time, we honor Husserl’s insight that “habit and free motivation intertwine.” As the article shows, resolution of the relationship between habit and free motivation requires recognition of nonlinguistic corporeal concepts that develop in concert with synergies of meaningful movement, concepts and synergies achieved not by embodied minds but mindful bodies. Maxine Sheets-JohnstoneRosenberg & Sellierarticledynamic patternshabits of mindkinesthesiatactile-kinesthetic bodyinstinctsinfancy and early childhoodAestheticsBH1-301EthicsBJ1-1725ENFRITPhenomenology and Mind, Iss 6 (2016) |
institution |
DOAJ |
collection |
DOAJ |
language |
EN FR IT |
topic |
dynamic patterns habits of mind kinesthesia tactile-kinesthetic body instincts infancy and early childhood Aesthetics BH1-301 Ethics BJ1-1725 |
spellingShingle |
dynamic patterns habits of mind kinesthesia tactile-kinesthetic body instincts infancy and early childhood Aesthetics BH1-301 Ethics BJ1-1725 Maxine Sheets-Johnstone On the Origin, Nature, and Genesis of Habit |
description |
This article details fundamental aspects of habits, beginning with the fact that habits are dynamic patterns that are learned, and that in coincidence with this learning, habits of mind are formed, as in the formation of expectations, thus of certain if/then relationships. It points out that, in quite the opposite manner of the practice of phenomenology, the strange is made familiar in the formation of habits. It shows how clear-sighted recognition of the seminal significance of movement and phenomenologically-grounded understandings of movement are essential to understandings of habits and the habits of mind that go with them. The article differentiates non-developmentally achieved habits from developmentally achieved habits, but elucidates too the relationship between instincts and habits. It elucidates the relationship in part by showing how, contra Merleau-Ponty, “in man” there is a “natural sign”—or rather, natural signs. By relinquishing an adultist stance and delving into our common infancy and early childhood, we recognize the need for what Husserl terms a “regressive inquiry” and thereby recover ‘natural signs’ such as smiling, laughing, and crying. At the same time, we honor Husserl’s insight that “habit and free motivation intertwine.” As the article shows, resolution of the relationship between habit and free motivation requires recognition of nonlinguistic corporeal concepts that develop in concert with synergies of meaningful movement, concepts and synergies achieved not by embodied minds but mindful bodies.
|
format |
article |
author |
Maxine Sheets-Johnstone |
author_facet |
Maxine Sheets-Johnstone |
author_sort |
Maxine Sheets-Johnstone |
title |
On the Origin, Nature, and Genesis of Habit |
title_short |
On the Origin, Nature, and Genesis of Habit |
title_full |
On the Origin, Nature, and Genesis of Habit |
title_fullStr |
On the Origin, Nature, and Genesis of Habit |
title_full_unstemmed |
On the Origin, Nature, and Genesis of Habit |
title_sort |
on the origin, nature, and genesis of habit |
publisher |
Rosenberg & Sellier |
publishDate |
2016 |
url |
https://doaj.org/article/c44f8a55c2534c70a8a488e0f4fa208c |
work_keys_str_mv |
AT maxinesheetsjohnstone ontheoriginnatureandgenesisofhabit |
_version_ |
1718398087847739392 |